Joseph
S. Lucas and Donald A. Yerxa, Editors
Historically
Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society
January/February
2005
Volume
VI, Number 3
Franklin
Knight, "President's Corner"
Anthony
Harkins, "The Hillbilly in the American Imagination"
POSTMODERNISM
AND HISTORICAL INQUIRY: THREE VIEWS
--C.
Behan McCullagh, "Postmodernism and the Truth of History"
--Beverley
Southgate, "Postmodernism and Historical Inquiry: Spoiled for Choice?"
--Willie
Thompson, "Postmodernism and Historiography"
THE
USES OF CLASSICAL HISTORY FOR CONTEMPORARY THEMES: A FORUM
--J.
Peter Euben, "The Uses of Classical History for Contemporary Themes"
--Richard
Ned Lebow, "Ethics and Foreign Policy"
--Danielle
Allen, "Response to Euben and Lebow"
--Mary
Lefkowitz, "Response to Euben and Lebow"
--Josiah
Ober, "Democracy, Knowledge, and Moral Change"
--Loren
J. Samons II, "Ancient Lessons for (Post)Moderns?"
--Barry
Strauss, "Commentary on Euben and Lebow"
--Carol
Thomas, "Captured by Greece? Terms of Imprisonment"
--J.
Peter Euben, "Responses to Responses"
--Richard
Ned Lebow, "The Dangers of Rampant Individualism"
William
Anthony Hay, "Reconsidering Herbert Butterfield"
Harold
D. Woodman, "In Memoriam: Daniel J. Boorstin"
Historically
Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society
Volume
VI, Number 3
THE
PRESIDENT’S CORNER
Franklin
W. Knight
Let
me begin my first official message to my colleagues by admitting candidly
that being elected president of the Historical Society constitutes for
me both a signal honor and an intimidating challenge.
The
honor derives from the rewarding experience of participating with a varied
and dynamic group of scholars, along with the humbling confidence that
many of these, either misguided or simply malicious, have faith in my ability
to lead this august group over the next two years. I joined the Society
because I share its fundamental belief in open intellectual dialogue largely
devoid of hollow posturing and vapid ideological grandstanding. The Historical
Society has always subordinated conventional hierarchies and disciplinary
categories in its unyielding quest for intellectual integrity. At the first
general meeting in Boston in 1999, our esteemed president, Eugene Genovese,
boldly encouraged members of the Society to “refuse to impose a particular
ideology, or to privilege trivial work over significant work under the
guise of righting old wrongs.” And he certainly connected fully with his
audience (as I recall) when he continued, “In women’s history, Afro-American
history, and no few other subjects, we distinguish the significant issues
from the spurious, distinguish world-historical developments from the parochial,
and, above all, distinguish interpretations based on conscientious research
from ideological pronouncements based on ‘theories’ that turn out to be
little more than opinions.” That magnificent Patton-like exhortation motivated
the entire audience to greater endeavors. It certainly moved me greatly.
I have, over the years, enjoyed the biennial meetings for their uninhibited
approach to serious discussions and spontaneous camaraderie. That more
than justified my modest subscription and zealous participation. I harbored
no great ambition to rise above the anonymity of the Lake Woebegone-like
majority. Moreover, everyone knows that “heavy is the head that wears a
crown.” I had led other organizations of scholars before and the experience
was always sobering. But having been called to service, like a superannuated
plough horse, there is no other recourse but to reconcile experience and
ability and execute the duties required. Anything less would be unacceptable.
The
intimidating nature of the challenge of this office is self-evident. First,
it is invariably difficult to follow in the wake of giants. The Historical
Society has been extremely fortunate to have had a succession of intellectual
giants as presidents—Eugene D. Genovese, George Huppert, and Peter Coclanis
—and each has made a tremendous contribution to the development of the
Society as well as the formal discipline. They were all bold, imaginative,
energetic, and creative leaders who accomplished a great deal in a very
short time. Despite the lofty sentiment of the American Declaration of
Independence, all men are not created equal. Nor will social, political,
and biological engineering result in a common equality. Napoleon Bonaparte
made France great, politically as well as territorially. He was followed
(not directly) by Napoleon III whose political and military careers constituted
a succession of unmitigated disasters for France. This led the perceptive
François Guizot to scoff, “Because we have a Napoleon the Great
must we now have a Napoleon the Little?” I will work hard to avoid a comparable
observation. We all do the best that we can within the limits of our varied
abilities and the unpredictable circumstances of our tenure. The important
requirement in any position of responsibility is to be the best that one
can be. I pledge to do that in my capacity as your president.
Good
intentions, however, will not eliminate the inescapable problems of any
organization. No association, however large and financially secure, can
afford to rest on its laurels and become prematurely complacent about the
future. The Historical Society is neither rich nor large. It has undoubtedly
accomplished much in its few years of existence, and we can justifiably
congratulate ourselves and take pride in these magnificent achievements.
The Society has rapidly congregated an impressive number of enthusiastic,
internationally distributed members and a small, devoted, miracle-working
staff. It has created a highly respectable, well-received journal that
is exciting to read, reflecting both the consistent quality of the submissions
and the exemplary, exacting professionalism of Elizabeth Fox-Genovese.
Historically Speaking, the Society’s bulletin, skillfully edited
by Joseph Lucas and Donald Yerxa, stands without peer for lucidity, originality,
and lively short articles of topical currency. The user-friendly web page
is updated regularly. All this represents the good news.
We
have much to do—and you will note the deliberate use of the first person
plural. Success in our goals will only come from the cooperative assertions
of all members of the Historical Society. No president, however gifted
or lucky, can do it all alone. Ultimate success will depend on each and
every member putting forth fully in the collective efforts required. This
is of paramount importance. Please send to the staff and to me your ideas.
We promise to take every idea seriously and respond as best we can. Participate
in the general meetings for fellowship and for profit. Let us embrace the
urging of President John Kennedy and think not what the Historical Society
can do for you but what you can you for the Historical Society. And there
is a lot that you can do.
We
need to make a concerted drive to expand our membership, especially among
younger scholars and graduate students. The virtues of youth are many and
attracting more young scholars to the Society will benefit all of us. Without
the constant infusion of new blood we will lose our cutting-edge intellectual
excitement as well as the inherent dynamism required to resolve the issues
that will inevitably confront the Society. Membership in the Historical
Society is one of the last true bargains in the academic world. We need
to share the news among our colleagues, in our departments, and at gatherings
of the other organizations to which we belong. Evangelism in the cause
of good is always a virtue.
We
need to strengthen the financial foundation of the Society. We urge our
members to pay their regular dues promptly and to consider the practical
advantages of life membership. We have a good base in our present membership,
and I warmly congratulate those who have opted for lifetime membership
in the Historical Society. The staff will vigorously explore new avenues
of support from foundations and other institutional benefactors around
the world. We have a very good track record of institutional support without
which we would not exist. But that is not enough. It is imperative that
we think seriously over the next two years of creating our own endowment.
Of course, an endowment per se is no guarantee of permanence, but
it does enhance greatly the eventual possibility of economic flexibility
and autonomy. In any case, the important point is to encourage our present
generation to make a start, and earmarking contributions to the endowment
fund is one way to ensure its reality.
We
also need to revitalize our regional seminars and conferences. Since the
Society meets biennially it is imperative that the members keep active
during the intersession period with activities that reflect and extend
the goals of the Society. Some regions are more active than others, but
for the regions of lesser activity, a good idea might be to begin with
seminars on the works, published or unpublished, of local members. Such
activity would not only strengthen the historical community at large but
also mutually enhance our individual work.
Another
idea would be to explore at the regional level aspects of the upcoming
theme of the Historical Society conference in Chapel Hill, North Carolina,
scheduled for June 1–4, 2006: “Globalization, Empire, and Imperialism in
Historical Perspective.” As the call for papers indicates, this is a subject
that has attracted enormous attention over the last few years and on which
the literature is frightfully extensive. The inexhaustible dimensions of
this heated debate could provide fruitful preparation for what we hope
will be another exciting and illuminating series of discussions at Chapel
Hill next year.
One
of the goals of the Historical Society is to encourage scholarly works
fully accessible to the general public. That is part of our mission statement.
We think we already do this in both our publications The Journal of
the Historical Society and Historically Speaking. But there
is room for new efforts. There are two areas in which I would like to see
some programmatic development in the next two years.
The
first idea is a series of short summer seminars designed for doctoral students
writing their dissertations. Here we could try to bring together a manageable
number of national and international doctoral candidates exploring a common
theme along with some faculty in the specialty, who could create an intellectually
fertile atmosphere. Such an activity would advance scholarship as well
as further cement our collegial relations in an increasingly global academic
community.
The
second idea would be to try to find sponsors for bringing college and high
school teachers to the biennial meetings of the Historical Society. The
format of the meetings is perfect for this dialogue. The principal theme
is advertised more than two years in advance. The location moves around
the country. A large proportion of the papers are available online before
the meeting. Most sessions are dominated by free-flowing discussions in
an intimate, collegial atmosphere rather than the preacher-and-congregation
format so utterly subversive of public participation and contemptuously
dismissive of intellectual equality. At the Historical Society the audience
is the star. In such an atmosphere good ideas can genuinely find root.
Over
the next two years I hope that you will frequently send to me and to the
staff ideas and initiatives that you feel we should pursue. Tell us what
you are doing and how your activity advances the mission of the Historical
Society. We truly welcome your input. This is your Historical Society and
we are all going together on this great intellectual journey. With your
help the next years should be enormously exciting ones.
Franklin
W. Knight, the Leonard and Helen R. Stulman Professor of History at the
Johns Hopkins University, is the fourth president of the Historical Society.
He has published eight books and eighty-two scholarly articles, chapters,
and forewords in books dealing with Caribbean and Latin American history,
including Slave Society in Cuba During the Nineteenth Century (University
of Wisconsin Press, 1970); The Caribbean: The Genesis of a Fragmented
Nationalism (Oxford University Press, 1990); Atlantic Port Cities:
Economy, Culture and Society in the Atlantic World, 1650–1850 (University
of Tennessee Press, 1991); Slave Societies in the Caribbean (UNESCO/Macmillan,
1997); and the forthcoming Contemporary Caribbean Cultures and Societies
in a Global Context (2005). Professor Knight is a past president of
the Latin American Studies Association.
THE
HILLBILLY IN THE AMERICAN IMAGINATION
Anthony
Harkins
Musicians
today like Dwight Yoakam and Marty Stuart call their brand of “roots” country
“hillbilly.” Snuffy Smith remains a popular comic strip seventy
years after its creation. Nearly everyone can immediately identify the
first few notes of the banjo song from the 1972 film Deliverance.
And the Fox television show The Simple Life has garnered a huge
audience partly by playing off of stereotypes about plain folk in the Arkansas
hills. The hillbilly has been one of the most pervasive and enduring icons
of American popular culture.
The
hillbilly has served such a role because this image and identity is a fundamentally
ambiguous one that includes both positive and negative features of the
American past and present. Central to this ambiguity is its unique racial
and cultural status. As a depiction of what I call a “white other”—impoverished,
isolated, and primitive Americans who nevertheless possess a supposedly
pure Anglo-Saxon Protestant heritage—“hillbilly” signifies both rugged
individualism and stubborn backwardness; strong family and kin networks
but also inbreeding and bloody feuds; a closeness to nature and the land
but also the potential for wild savagery; a clear sense of self and place
but, at the same time, crippling geographic and cultural isolation .
. . .
Anthony
Harkins is assistant professor of history at Western Kentucky University
and author of Hillbilly: A Cultural History of an American Icon (Oxford
University Press, 2004).
<top>
Join
the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking
Historically
Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society
January/February
2005
Volume VI, Number 3
POSTMODERNISM
AND HISTORICAL INQUIRY:THREE VIEWS
HAS
POSTMODERNISM RUN ITS COURSE? After all the sound and fury did postmodernist
thinking make any substantive impact on historical inquiry? We asked three
authors of recently published books on postmodernism and history to offer
their thoughts.
POSTMODERNISM
AND THE TRUTH OF HISTORY
C.
Behan McCullagh
The
great contribution of postmodern thought to our assessment of human knowledge
has been to remind us that our knowledge is generally couched in language,
so it does not mirror the world as we believe most of our perceptions do.
Our knowledge is constructed from elements of our culture, employing concepts
and forms of argument that we have learned and believe to be appropriate.
Our descriptions of the world reflect our interests, values, and purposes,
so they are not perfectly impartial and complete accounts of the subjects
they describe. They seldom capture every detail of the subjects we describe,
so they are, in that sense, almost always incomplete. Furthermore, the
meanings of the words we use, which depend upon their relations to other
words, cannot be fixed with any precision, so that the descriptions are
always vague.
These
are true and important points, and they have been used by some to cast
doubt upon the truth of historical descriptions. Frank Ankersmit, Beverley
Southgate, and Alun Munslow, for example, have all denied that general
interpretations of past events can be true for these reasons, though they
have, rather inconsistently, allowed that descriptions of particular historical
events can be true. Robert Berkhofer and Keith Jenkins have gone further,
arguing that when descriptions of particular historical facts are embedded
in an interpretative narrative, they fail to provide us with reliable information
about the past.1
If
these facts make narrative interpretations of the past unbelievable, then
they make descriptions of particular events incredible as well. Why on
earth should we think that historical knowledge, a culturally bound linguistic
construction in the present, bears any particular relation to past events
at all?
The
trouble is, that if we insist upon skepticism toward statements of particular
facts about the past, we will have to abandon almost all the beliefs we
live by. In practice we have developed very reliable methods of distinguishing
statements about the world that are worthy of belief from those that are
not. To defend the credibility of singular descriptions, we should study
those methods and carefully consider their significance.2 .
. . .
C.
Behan McCullagh is a reader and associate professor in philosophy at La
Trobe University. His most recent book is The Logic of History: Putting
Postmodernism in Perspective (Routledge, 2004).
1 F.R.
Ankersmit, Narrative Logic: A Semantic Analysis of the Historian’s Language
(Martinus Nijhoff, 1983); Beverley Southgate, Postmodernism in History:
Fear or Freedom? (Routledge, 2003); Alun Munslow, The New History
(Pearson Education, 2003); Robert E. Berkhofer Jr., Beyond the Great
Story: History as Text and Discourse (Harvard University Press, 1995);
and Keith Jenkins, Refiguring History: New Thoughts on an Old Discipline
(Routledge, 2003).
2 This
I have attempted to do, most succinctly in my recent book The Logic
of History (Routledge, 2004).
<top>
Join
the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking
Historically
Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society
January/February
2005
Volume
VI, Number 3
POSTMODERNISM
AND HISTORICAL INQUIRY: SPOILED FOR CHOICE?†
Beverley
Southgate
For
me, postmodernism definitively arrived on December 12, 1997. On that day
the London Times reported that Prime Minister Tony Blair had gone
beyond the bounds of conventional diplomatic generosity by offering the
Irish negotiator Gerry Adams nothing less than “a choice of history.” For
a mere mortal to claim to have such dispensations in his gift may sound
extraordinarily hubristic to historians brought up to assert their own
unique rights over a past, the nature of which it was for them, and only
them, to determine. But for those attempting to assess the implications
of postmodernism for historical inquiry, Blair’s offer does at least make
a start. And as we grope our way through something of a conceptual fog,
the key word “choice” does provide one useful beacon.
What
Blair implied with his offer of historical choice was that, while the events
of the past (with all their anger and frustration and violence) are undoubtedly
there—or rather here, in our present—what actually matters is not their
existence, their presence per se, but rather our responses to them.
We can look at them, respond to them, remember them, either in such a way
as will lead to further disruption or one that will facilitate reconciliation.
What Adams had, and what historians have, is a choice of narrative—a choice
of the way to “emplot” those past events or put them in a story that leads
from them, through our present, and forward to the future.
That
seems to me to get to the heart of what postmodernism implies for historical
inquiry—where postmodernism represents an attempt to theorize, and
make some intellectual sense of, our actual situation in postmodernity;
and postmodernity I take to be simply a chronological category,
with disputable boundaries like any other, but one that enables us at least
provisionally to locate ourselves in the ever-rolling stream of time .
. . .
†
For comments on an earlier draft, I am grateful to Dennis Brown and John
Ibbett.
Beverley
Southgate is reader emeritus in the history of ideas at the University
of Hertfordshire. His most recent book is Postmodernism in History:
Fear or Freedom? (Routledge, 2003).
<top>
Join
the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking
Historically
Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society
January/February
2005
Volume VI, Number 3
POSTMODERNISM
AND HISTORIOGRAPHY
Willie
Thompson
The
theoretical origins of postmodernism are primarily located in the poststructuralist
philosophy that emerged in France during the later 1960s and blossomed
in the 1970s. At the end of the decade the initially separate concepts
of postmodernism and poststructuralism coalesced, the critical text in
this regard being Jean-François Lyotard’s La Condition Postmoderne:
report sur le savoir, appearing in 1979. In it he defined postmodernism
as an “incredulity towards metanarrative.”
In
the historiographical context, while debts are acknowledged to writers
such as Jacques Lacan (psychoanalyst), Hayden White (historian of ideas),
Jacques Derrida (philosopher/critic), unquestionably the principal influence
has been Michel Foucault (1926–1984). Foucault always denied being a postmodernist
or postructuralist, and indeed ridiculed anyone who described him in these
terms, but that may have been no more than a postmodern joke; nobody has
done more to establish postmodernism as an intellectual presence. Foucault,
always working within a linguistic framework and a concept of all-pervasive
power relations constituted through discourse (it was he who popularized
the term in that sense), surveyed a series of broad themes such as madness,
medicine, social science, penal regimes, and sexuality, and had interesting
things to say on all of them as well as much of dubious value. His publishers
have claimed him as the most influential thinker of the 20th century, and
he has been the principal source of inspiration to historians of a postmodern
sensibility, as well as to those who do not accept the validity of his
approach but have found useful insights in his writings.
Postmodernism
as we have come to know it can therefore be treated appropriately as the
product of a great disillusion: disillusion with science both social and
physical, disillusion with the idea of historical progress, disillusion
with the possibility of far-reaching social change. Its attraction was
enhanced greatly by the dramatic collapse of the Soviet-style regimes,
polities that purported (however falsely) to embody such ideas and aspirations
. . . .
Willie
Thompson is visiting professor at the University of Northumbria at Newcastleupon-
Tyne. He is the author of Postmodernism and History (Palgrave, 2003).
<top>
Join
the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking
Historically
Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society
January/February
2005
Volume VI, Number 3
THE
USES OF CLASSICAL HISTORY FOR CONTEMPORARY THEMES: A FORUM
OVER
THE PAST DECADE, the state of the field of classical history—particularly
its relevance in the “curricula wars”—has been a matter of intense debate,
spilling occasionally outside the academy in jeremiads like Who Killed
Homer? The Demise of Classical Education and the Recovery of Greek Wisdom.
The authors of two recently published books, Richard Ned Lebow and J. Peter
Euben, make the case that intense engagement with ancient Greek thought
continues to pay dividends, particularly as we assess contemporary political
thought and public policy.
Lebow
and Euben anchor our forum on “The Uses of Classical History for Contemporary
Themes” with essays drawn, respectively, from The Tragic Vision of
Politics: Ethics, Interests, and Orders (Cambridge University Press,
2003) and Platonic Noise (Princeton University Press, 2003). We
invited six distinguished classicists (Danielle Allen, Mary Lefkowitz,
Josiah Ober, Loren J. Samons, II, Barry Strauss, and Carol Thomas) to respond.
Lebow and Euben conclude the forum with their replies.
With
heavy hearts we report the passing of Howard Nostrand, emeritus professor
of romance languages at the University of Washington, who had planned to
participate in our forum. Our sympathies are extended to his family and
colleagues.
<top>
Join
the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking
Historically
Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society
January/February
2005
Volume VI, Number 3
THE
USES OF CLASSICAL HISTORY FOR CONTEMPORARY THEMES†
J.
Peter Euben
I do
not think we should “use” classical history (or in my case classical political
thought) to address modern thinkers insofar as the idea of use furthers
the instrumentalization of education and promotes both presentism and didacticism.
By presentism I mean the acceptance of current intellectual fashions and
cultural identities as the necessary context for reflection on the present;
the supposition that contemporary theories and methods represent the epitome
of sophistication and self-consciousness; and the dismissal of what is
alien, unfamiliar, and radical under the sign of pragmatism, practicality,
and realism.
By
didacticism I mean two things. The first is having texts, events, or cultures
say what one wants them to say rather than allowing them to interrogate
the questions, interpretative strategies, and intellectual categories one
brings to them. The second is transforming canonical texts into a catalogue
of virtues.
Both
aspects of didacticism were present on both sides of the “culture wars.”
Perhaps that helps explain the odd confluence between cultural conservatives
who “used” classical texts to derive lessons by which to chastise their
multiculturalist critics and those multiculturalist critics who agreed
that those texts contained those lessons and condemned them for it.1 For
both combatants Socrates became a ventriloquized dummy rather than a gadfly
or midwife, and Platonic dialogues became covert monologues in which answers
were purchased at the cost of deepening the questions.
I am
not sure that idealizing “the Glory that was Greece” is any more attractive
an alternative than presentism and didacticism. At least that is so when
such idealizations are used to promote slavish imitation, nostalgia, or
an aestheticism that relegates the Greeks to decorative appendages, like
some expensive piece of jewelry that accessorizes an outfit.
Rather
than marginalize, mimic, or monumentalize “the Greeks” we need to engage
them in many senses of that word: to occupy the attention of, be bound
to by promise or contract, become betrothed to; but also to become interlocked
with (as with gears), bring into conflict, battle with, and contest. Part
of what I have in mind is captured by Nietzsche’s insistence that classical
studies must be “untimely”—that is to say, acting counter to our time and
thereby acting on our time, and let us hope for the benefit of a time to
come.2 Being untimely means living in two times at once, our own and that
of some other time (for him it was ancient Greece). The alternative is
being captured by the moment and settling for the familiar. Such thinking
with and outside history sustains our capacity for surprise and renewal
and makes us aware of how and what about the world escapes the categories
we suppose captures it . . . .
† Roxanne
Euben, Donald Moon, and George Shulman made invaluable suggestions for
improvement of this essay.
J.
Peter Euben is Research Professor of Political Science, adjunct professor
of classics, and the Kenan Distinguished Faculty Fellow in Ethics at Duke
University. His most recent book is Platonic Noise (Princeton University
Press, 2003).
1 I
discussed this at length in Chapter One of Corrupting Youth (Princeton
University Press, 1997).
2 Friedrich
Nietzsche, “On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for Life,” in Daniel
Breazeale, ed., Untimely Meditations (Cambridge University Press,
1997), 60.
<top>
Join
the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking
Historically
Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society
January/February
2005
Volume VI, Number 3
ETHICS
AND FOREIGN POLICY
Richard
Ned Lebow
In
the Western world, there is a widely accepted distinction between public
and private morality. We consider it wrong to lie, but smile knowingly
when we first hear the old adage that a diplomat is an honest man who lies
in the interest of his country. But how do we feel about leaders who lie
to their own people in the name of national security, or actively support
murderous dictatorships because they are anti-communist or protect American
interests? Is any action defensible if it enhances national security or
the national interest? Is the distinction between public and private morality
a useful, perhaps necessary, one in a world where hostile forces plot our
destruction? Or is it merely a convenient rationalization for unscrupulous
and self-serving behavior?
As
currently formulated, there is no way to adjudicate between competing claims
of ethics and security. The demand for ethical foreign policies is rebuffed
by the assertion that physical security is the essential precondition for
the kind of society that makes ethical life possible. The counter-argument
that one cannot produce or sustain an ethical society by immoral means
provokes the rejoinder that international politics does not allow this
kind of luxury. The controversy quickly returns to its starting point.
But are the imperatives of security really at odds with the canons of ethics?
Is a nation always best served by hard-nosed self-interest? If it can be
shown that ethical behavior is more conducive —perhaps even essential—to
national security, the advocates of Realpolitik could be challenged
on their home turf.
I contend,
pace Thucydides, that interests —of individuals or states—presuppose
identities, and that actors can develop identities only through membership
in societies. All functioning societies in turn rest on some ethical foundation.
Ethics accordingly enables identities and interests. It follows that maintenance
of the principles of justice that sustain societies is a primary interest
of all actors, including states . . . .
Richard
Ned Lebow is the James O. Freedman Presidential Professor of Government
at Dartmouth College. His most recent book is The Tragic Vision of
Politics: Ethics, Interests, and Orders (Cambridge University Press,
2003). He is president of the International Society of Political Psychology.
<top>
Join
the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking
Historically
Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society
January/February
2005
Volume VI, Number 3
RESPONSE
TO EUBEN AND LEBOW
Danielle
Allen
The
relative usefulness of any body of knowledge is a question for adults about
how to pack their bags for a journey through unmapped land. Every generation
answers differently the question of what it should take into the future.
We should note that both Euben and Lebow argue for the value of Greek (read
Athenian) history and culture; neither advocates for Rome. Yet 200 years
ago, the equation worked in just the other direction. The authors of the
Federalist Papers thought Athens was relevant only for its experience
in organizing a multi-city alliance, this perhaps being a precursor to
federalism; Rome was the point of reference for the internal structure
of the new republic. This change across American generations confirms our
sense that there is no single, final use for classical history that justifies
its value once and for all. Its relevance is properly re-argued by each
generation; this is how each generation determines what it needs to know
and why.
Both
Euben and Lebow argue that we currently need Athenian history for ethical
and political reasons: so that we can resolve the paradox between ethics
and security (though I’m not sure the Athenian case yields an answer quite
as easily as Lebow proposes); so that we can learn the limits of human
action and agency and become more egalitarian citizens at home and abroad
(Euben). Interestingly, the early American intellectuals looked to Rome
for lessons about institutions, whereas we seem now to look to Greece
for moral culture . . . .
Danielle
Allen is professor of classics and political science at the University
of Chicago. She became dean of the University’s Humanities Division in
July 2004. A winner of a MacArthur Foundation grant in 2001, Allen has
written The World of Prometheus: The Politics of Punishing in Democratic
Athens (Princeton University Press, 2000).
<top>
Join
the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking
Historically
Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society
January/February
2005
Volume VI, Number 3
RESPONSE
TO EUBEN AND LEBOW
Mary
Lefkowitz
As
Peter Euben says, “we have no choice but to engage the Greeks because we
have done so in the past and continue to do so today.” As both he and Richard
Ned Lebow suggest in their essays, we remain connected to the ancient Greeks
because they framed the essential questions we are still grappling with:
How can we tell right from wrong? What do we do when our individual needs
conflict with those of our society? How can we describe and characterize
the forces beyond our control? How can we bring ourselves to recognize
the limitations of our abilities to come to terms with these questions?
Like Euben and Lebow, I believe that ancient Greek writers still can help
us understand these problems, even though ultimately they cannot always
help us to find practical solutions.
Euben
and Lebow concentrate on major social trends, but the Greek writers whose
works they discuss concentrate mainly on the actions of certain individuals,
the people (almost exclusively male) who are in positions of power, and
who have the ability to affect the lives of others. Although Thucydides
in his speeches explains thoughts and motives in abstract terms, most of
his history of the Peloponnesian War consists of narrative about the actions
of men and armies. As Plato knew, stories are easier to understand and
remember than abstractions. Educated Greeks and (later) Romans, boys and
also some girls, learned about human emotions, war, and death primarily
from the Iliad, which they studied and memorized and copied out
at school. In the 5th century B.C. Athenian audiences learned about how
individuals confront the forces beyond their control from the dramas that
were performed each year at state expense during the festival of the god
Dionysus.
It
was from these texts that they heard narratives about atê,
the delusion that leads mortals to destruction. Aristotle was talking about
ate when he spoke about the hamartia or error in judgment
that causes a hero in tragedy to make terrible mistakes—the translation
“tragic flaw” is inaccurate and misleading.1 If I were asked what was the
most important lesson we could still learn from the Greeks, I would say
it is their understanding of atê as a force that has a profound
and lasting effect on almost every human life. To them, being mortal was
to be vulnerable to delusion. Atê is particularly dangerous
because at first she appears to be seductive and appealing .
. . .
Mary
Lefkowitz is the Andrew W. Mellon Professor in the Humanities at Wellesley
College. Her most recent book is Greek Gods, Human Lives (Yale University
Press, 2003).
1
Poetics 1453a 8–17; see also R.N. Lebow, The Tragic Vision of Politics
(Cambridge University Press, 2003), 131–32.
<top>
Join
the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking
Historically
Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society
January/February
2005
Volume
VI, Number 3
DEMOCRACY,
KNOWLEDGE,AND MORAL CHANGE
Josiah
Ober
Whenever
someone claims that the history of “the Greeks” can teach us about ourselves,
we should ask “which Greeks?” Most ancient Greek communities are frankly
irrelevant to the considerations brought forward by Euben, Lebow, and other
modern theorists who engage with Greek political culture. In the classical
and Hellenistic periods there were roughly 1500 Greek poleis. The great
majority of these were what Greek historians call Normalpoleis—which
means that they had very small populations (averaging a few hundred to
a few thousand persons) and controlled very small territories (a few dozen
to few hundred square kilometers). These tiny communities have no continuous
recorded history and their material culture (from what we can make out
from scattered hints and remains) was a mix of the “disembedded” economy
discussed by Lebow and a much more traditional, regionally-centered, family-
and neighbor-based pattern of exchange. They were face-to-face societies,
in which most people knew (for good or ill) one another’s characters and
habits. Most of these Normalpoleis were not fully independent: some were
forced to join alliance systems (e.g. the Peloponnesian League or Athenian
Empire, as discussed by Thucydides); some organized themselves into sophisticated
regional systems (koina), sustained by shared economic interests,
religious practices, and political institutions. The Normalpolis is of
great interest to Greek historians, but it is of no greater moment than
any other traditional pre-modern society to contemporary political thought.
Were the Normalpolis the sum of Greek culture, there would be no special
place for Greek studies in the post-ancient world, no interest in applying
Greek history to modern concerns, and this set of essays would never have
been conceived.1
A few
Greek poleis were radically different and much bigger. These super-poleis
include (with the exception of Melos) all of the poleis mentioned by Lebow
and Euben and virtually all poleis that anyone but a Greek historian is
likely to mention: e.g. Syracuse, Corinth, Corcyra, Thebes, Sparta, and,
of course, Athens.2 With a total population of perhaps a quarter-million
and a home territory (not counting imperial possessions) of some 2500 square
kilometers, Athens was roughly 50–100 times the size of a Normalpolis.
The Athenian economy was much more “disembedded” than that of the Normalpolis,
and Athens, qua polis, was much too large to be a face-to-face society.
Its social and political institutions were correspondingly complex. Athens
was also, unlike most other classical poleis, large or small, a stable
democracy.3 In the 18th century, oligarchic/ aristocratic Sparta was the
super-polis that attracted favorable attention
from theorists. But since the mid-19th century, it has been Athens—anomalous
in terms of its size and its
democratic political culture, the latter of which has been of primary concern
to political thinkers. The point is that today, when we say “the Greeks,”
we usually mean “the democratic Athenians”—and it is important to remember
that Athens was not a community that manifested a typical “Greek culture.”
It is not generic “Greek culture” that is relevant to modernity; it is
the culture that developed in Athens and spread to other poleis in the
late classical and Hellenistic periods.4 .
. . .
Josiah
Ober is David Magie ’97 Class of 1897 Professor of Classics at Princeton
University. His most recent book is Political Dissent in Democratic
Athens: Intellectual Critics of Popular Rule (Princeton University Press,
1998).
1
Eberhard Ruschenbusch, Untersuchungen zu Staat und Politik in Griechenland
vom 7.–4. Jh. v. Chr. (AKU, 1978); Mogens Hansen, Introduction to
an Inventory of ‘Poleis’: Symposium August 23–26, 1995 (Munksgaard,
1996).
2
One possible exception is Aphytis in the Chersonese, which will come to
the mind of close readers of Aristotle’s Politics, as the model
of a “best type” democracy.
3
Of course stability is a relative term, but unlike Syracuse, Corinth, or
Thebes, for example, which experienced democratic interludes, Athens was
almost always governed democratically from 508 B.C. through 322 B.C. and
more sporadically thereafter. Athenian democracy was not ossified; situations
changed over time, but the core values —commitments to freedom, equality,
and security —remained identifiably the same over this period.
4
The agricultural community (“hoplite republic”) and traditional values
assumed to be typical of the Normalpolis become the foundation of “Western
civilization” in the work of some conservatives who distrust Athens as
a non-virtuous “radical democracy” yet idolize the cultural products produced
in Athens. Their solution is to speak generically of “Greek” wisdom, culture,
literature, and so on. See, for example, Victor Davis Hanson and John Heath,
Who Killed Homer? The Demise of Classical Education and the Recovery
of Greek Wisdom (Free Press, 1998).
<top>
Join
the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking
Historically
Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society
January/February
2005
Volume VI, Number 3
ANCIENT
LESSONS FOR (POST)MODERNS?
Loren
J. Samons II
Perhaps
Thucydides continues to seem so smart and so relevant because he lived
and wrote in a time before the invention of jargon. That, at least, was
my first thought upon reading these essays.
Two
fundamental questions confront anyone interested in whether classical history
can be used for contemporary themes. First, does man have a nature? Second,
were the classical Greek (and Roman) societies so alien from our own as
to make comparisons and analogies between the two hopelessly flawed?
Ultimately,
the first question subsumes the second. Because if man does have a nature—as
I, like Thucydides, believe he does—then that nature will allow us to draw
useful lessons from other men’s experiences, as long as we make an (admittedly
imperfect) attempt to allow for the peculiar cultural and historical factors
that operated on that nature in different periods. Conversely, anyone who
does not believe that man has a nature cannot believe that the study of
antiquity will be relevant for us today: i.e., if everything about
us is culturally determined and shaped, if nurture trumps nature at every
turn, then only the study of our own (and our immediately previous) environment
and circumstances will be relevant and useful.
But
if I am arguing that the study of classical antiquity can be “relevant
and useful,” precisely in what ways is this study supposed to help us?
Here, I think, our authors have let us down—or rather, they have not been
as bold as I would like them to have been. For example, Euben’s call for
“engagement” with the Greeks—an engagement that can “invigorate” our discourse
or “deepen” questions and understanding—frankly leaves me cold. I expect
virtually everything I read to sharpen my mind, so I cannot see how this
claim puts ancient history in a privileged position. In any case, how precisely
does one tell whether a discourse has been “invigorated” or not? And how
deep does a question need to be before we can start to answer it? I suppose
that questions can be infinitely deep, and that discourse can be infinitely
vigorous; thus, at what points do we satisfy ourselves that we have attained
sufficiently deepened questions and invigorated debate so that we can start
searching for answers and drawing conclusions?
Euben,
I believe, would say that I am missing the point. That “political knowledge”
is (or should be) “constituted discursively,” and that “answers” are not
nearly so important as questions. But that doesn’t offer much help to those
who would ask, for example, whether it is a good idea for the United States
to attempt to impose democratic governments on previously undemocratic
states. Is our “knowledge” on this matter simply to be the result of the
current discourse on the subject? The Athenians certainly made foreign
policy based on a “discursive” process, but the actual results of these
decisions make one wonder about the wisdom of this procedure. Personally,
I would prefer to profit from, rather than imitate, the Athenians’ mistakes
. . . .
Loren
J. Samons II is associate professor of classical studies and associate
dean for students in the College of Arts and Sciences at Boston University.
His book What’s Wrong with Democracy? From Athenian Practice to American
Worship was published in October 2004 by the University of California
Press.
<top>
Join
the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking
Historically
Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society
January/February
2005
Volume
VI, Number 3
COMMENTARY
ON EUBEN AND LEBOW
Barry
Strauss
Once
upon a time in America a man sat in traffic and watched. And what he saw
was disturbing. Drivers were turning without signaling and, even worse,
they were running red lights. To add insult to injury (reportedly more
than 900 deaths and 20,000 injuries each year in the United States alone),
these same narcissists of the fast lane talked constantly of community
and family values.
It
was, the observer realized, a case of selfinterest run amok. “If only they
had read Thucydides,” he went on. “Then those drivers would realize that
rational self-interest entails a commitment to community.”
Meanwhile,
half a continent away, another man worked out at a health club. Like many
people, he did some of his best thinking at the gym. And today he reflected
on the paradox of contemporary American life. How could it be, he wondered,
that so many Americans were content to let their elected officials run
the country? And he used the word “elected” loosely, knowing how low voter
turnout rates are. Didn’t his fellow Americans know that while the citizen
cats were away, the elected mice were turning over the store to wealthy,
right-wing elites? Didn’t his fellow Americans care? After all, since they
worried enough about their bodies to keep fit, surely they loved their
country enough to exercise their duty as citizens on its behalf?
“Oh,”
he thought, “if only they would read Plato and Sophocles! Then they might
well engage with the promise and possibilities of classical democratic
citizenship. They would change their ways and make our representative government
into a direct democracy.”
I hope
that Euben and Lebow forgive me for choosing these two vignettes as a way
of summarizing their wise, learned, and stimulating essays. The authors
themselves offered the stories, and the tales are too wonderfully evocative
to let them pass by unnoticed. Each of the two essays from which they come
takes a different approach, but the pieces share a conviction: American
society suffers from an overdose of selfish individualism, but reading
the ancient Greek classics can help restore civility, community, and ethics
to the American polity, in both its foreign and domestic policies. Let
me take gentle issue both with the diagnosis and the prescription .
. . .
Barry
Strauss is professor of history and classics at Cornell University. He
is author of The Battle of Salamis: The Naval Encounter that Saved
Greece—and Western Civilization (Simon & Schuster, 2004).
<top>
Join
the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking
Historically
Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society
January/February
2005
Volume
VI, Number 3
CAPTURED
BY GREECE? TERMS OF IMPRISONMENT
Carol
Thomas
In
responding to these stimulating papers, I am assuming two hats. One is
my own as a student of Greek history; the other is that of Howard Nostrand,
a scholar of all things French. Nostrand’s most recent book, From the
Polarizing Mind-Set to Productive Discussion of Public Policy and Intercultural
and Interfaith Relations: Finding Common Ground (Mellen, 2003), provided
part of the context in which this forum emerged. Sadly, he died before
he could provide his own contribution. In framing my response, I build
upon both his wide-ranging interests and his own commitment to the forum’s
theme of looking to parallels and possible solutions in the ancient world.
Nostrand’s
book grew out of a concern that American society at present is driven by
a polarizing habit of mind that prompts confrontation, a condition as unproductive
as it is unpleasant. Nostrand described a latent, alternate mentality—what
he termed “a most resilient buried treasure”—in the ancient Greek pattern
of mind that sought balance between the two extremes of the bipolar habit
of mind. Balance exists at the mean between conflicting opposites, as,
for example, courage is the mean between cowardice and foolhardiness or
generosity is between avarice and lavishness. This mentality is more than
a philosophical concept: it is revealed concretely in the nature of Greek,
particularly Athenian, society during its classical age. Although Nostrand
accepted the view that the bipolar framework is embedded in the human biological
structure, he argued that the three-part mentality of seeking the mean
between polar opposites can be acquired by later cultures, especially since
the Greek heritage has been deeply incorporated into modern culture. Moreover,
the example of Greece has been called upon regularly, and found valuable,
by cultures addressing major challenges, both institutional and intellectual.
Modern
American society would be well advised to bring this latent mentality to
the surface.
Assuming
my own hat, I am reminded of a scheme employed in my edited study, Paths
from Ancient Greece (Brill, 1988), which explored the debt of later
cultures to classical Greece. That scheme recognized three chief categories
of influence: the exemplary, the configurative, and the legitimizing. These
categories can be applied to the studies of Nostrand, Lebow, and Euben
in order to appraise their positions.
According
to Nostrand, adoption of the Greek mentality that sought the golden mean
“could help to free our minds and our public discourse from the dominance
of the dualistic perception of reality . . . . [W]e could find means to
reclaim qualities of Athenian culture that can help us cope with our conflicts.”
If actualized, the requisite mentality, now only latent, could serve to
support departure from the immediate past as did those features of ancient
Greece incorporated into Renaissance Italian culture .
. . .
Carol
Thomas is professor of history at the University of Washington. Her most
recent book is Citadel to City State: The Transformation of Greece,
1200–700 BCE (Indiana University Press, 1999).
<top>
Join
the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking
Historically
Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society
January/February
2005
Volume
VI, Number 3
RESPONSES
TO RESPONSES
J.
Peter Euben
I begin
with an apology. Because Platonic Noise (the book from which my
initial remarks were drawn) is a series of essays that makes an argument
cumulatively rather than consecutively, I decided to make some general
methodological and political points as a way of inviting debate. That may
have been a mistake. I probably should have chosen one point and developed
it in more detail and with greater nuance. Absent that, conclusions become
mere assertions, and (hopefully) subtle arguments become mere platitudes.
Perhaps that would have assuaged Samons’s complaints that my call for engagement
leaves him “cold” and that I offer no alternative to Nussbaum’s liberal
cosmopolitanism except a banal conclusion about thinking with the Greeks
(though I must admit his churlish tone does not make me sanguine about
this). In fact, Platonic Noise has a chapter on Nietzsche that elaborates
the idea of engagement and another that develops a “critical cosmopolitanism”
as an alternative to Nussbaum’s.
Much
of Carol Thomas’s response is sensible, but I do have a few caveats, which
may or may not constitute more substantive disagreements. First of all,
I am not convinced that confrontation is always unproductive, as the civil
rights movement indicated. Second, I am more skeptical than she is that
“the human element of all cultures has been relatively constant” because
I am not sure how much or what kind of evidence could warrant such a claim,
and because the human element has too often proved to be a projection
of a particularly powerful class or culture. Finally, I wonder how much
the idea that the emotions are hardwired is not itself a cultural construct,
though I have no wish to associate myself with a know-nothing anti-positivism
. .
. .
<top>
Join
the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking
Historically
Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society
January/February
2005
Volume
VI, Number 3
THE
DANGERS OF RAMPANT INDIVIDUALISM
Richard
Ned Lebow
.
. . . Strauss
attributes red-light-running to bad roads and frustrated drivers. I am
not convinced, but even if I accept his explanation for the sake of the
argument, it still supports my larger point. When people run lights and
block intersections in heavy traffic, vehicular traffic grinds to a halt.
It is another example of how the untrammeled expression of self-interest
can be damaging to the very goals actors seek. Why should we believe that
drivers run red lights out of frustration with inadequate roads? What motivates
drivers is an empirical question that could be researched through interviews
and surveys. In the absence of solid empirical evidence, we can only speculate,
and arguments based on speculation are not very persuasive.
Neither
Peter Euben nor I see the Greek classics as a panacea. Knowledge of Thucydides
and Plato will not cure our social problems, or even point to possible
solutions. At best, it might make people more self-reflective, constrained
in their behavior, and open to other points of view. At the very least,
it might reduce the incidence of running red lights as the corpus of both
authors is heavy reading, even in translation, and time-consuming enough
to keep at least some people off the roads.
<top>
Join
the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking
Historically
Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society
January/February
2005
Volume
VI, Number 3
RECONSIDERING
HERBERT BUTTERFIELD
William
Anthony Hay
Contemporary
Americans inhabit a present-tense culture. Events beyond recent memory
lie shrouded in musty antiquity. While the past seems by definition irrelevant
to current realities, individuals and societies still understand their
identities by coming to terms with their history. Few have appreciated
this fact as well as Sir Herbert Butterfield (1900–1979), the British historian
and scholar of international relations who played a leading role in shaping
ongoing debates on historiography. Butterfield’s factual mastery built
upon a philosophical approach rooted in a keen awareness of the complexity
of human experience. Rejecting the conceit of the contemporary, he insisted
that true historical fervor lies in “love of the past for the sake of the
past” rather than in its immediate utility.1
Butterfield
was born and reared in a devout family of West Yorkshire Methodists. His
nonconformist upbringing instilled a deep skepticism of authority. Gaining
preferment either by cultivating the powerful or chasing after intellectual
fashions affronted his scholarly integrity. Though never active in the
church’s national affairs, Butterfield was a Methodist lay preacher in
his native Yorkshire and the villages surrounding Cambridge for almost
two decades. He received Anglican Communion in later years while holding
to his old faith and showed an acute sensitivity to other denominations,
including Roman Catholicism. Butterfield’s first work appeared during the
years when Graham Greene, Malcolm Muggeridge, and Evelyn Waugh began publishing,
and the collapse of secular idealism provides a common thread through these
very different lives. Maurice Cowling believed that Butterfield’s historical
thought reflected the sensibility of a Christian dissenter.2
Butterfield
began a life-long relationship with Cambridge University in 1919 when he
arrived as a student at Peterhouse College. He later became the Master
of Peterhouse and Vice Chancellor of the University before ending his career
as Regius Professor of History. Although his research focused primarily
on Hanoverian Britain, Butterfield’s interests ranged widely from the origins
of modern science to the problems of diplomacy and statecraft. He wrote
extensively on the interpretation of history, explaining once that “whenever
our ideas on some large historical theme are in a state of disorder, we
may find it useful to make ourselves acquainted with the historiography
of that particular subject.”3
Popular
undergraduate lectures and tutoring of aspiring academics gave Butterfield
great pedagogical influence. His death in 1979 brought fond reminiscences
from Cambridge alumni, and former students led the revisionist critique
of liberal and Marxist history that has transformed the study of British
history. The “High Politics” school of British historians that includes
Maurice Cowling, John Vincent, and J.C.D. Clark drew heavily on Butterfield’s
work, along with that of Michael Oakeshott and Sir Lewis Namier, in reexamining
political history. Rejecting what they saw as the liberal fiction of parliamentary
democracy—that power rests in institutions devised for its exercise—these
scholars examined instead the informal structures of debate and intrigue
that actually created policy. Their demonstration of how the interests
and ambitions of individual politicians drove events more than institutional
imperatives or the popular will contributed to a new sociology of politics.4
Butterfield’s heirs rejected both the Whig view of history and recent fashionable
theories in which social and economic forces determined events. Their emphasis
on narrative history and archival research revitalized the field, while
their analysis of politics as a practice incapable of being distilled into
universal laws offers insights on issues beyond British political history.
Butterfield’s
popular reputation derives largely from The Whig Interpretation of History
(1931), which examined the tendency among historians to adopt a Whig or
Protestant view of the past as a ratification, or even celebration, of
present ideals. What made the fallacy of organizing historical knowledge
around a debatable set of assumptions so common? The teleological approach
of Whig history provided convenient categories for explaining complex events,
and Butterfield noted that history became more Whig the more it was abridged.
The “pathetic fallacy” among historians of abstracting men and events and
judging them out of context provided another clue. Above all, Whig history
offered a meaningful and emotionally satisfying vision of events. However
insular or dated it might be for today’s readers, the flaws Whig history
shares with other interpretive schemes make Butterfield’s analysis especially
pertinent to current debates on historical study and the humanities.
Whig
history is an interpretation of England’s past crafted by a political party
in search of a pedigree—and with that pedigree an intellectual justification
for its claim to power. Its underlying assumption employs analogy to produce
a scheme that demonstrates the workings of progress so that the many strands
of the past converge neatly into the present. In this story, Whigs and
Protestants stand as the proponents of development toward a liberal, bourgeois
society that Catholics and Tories seek to impede. Butterfield describes
the popular misconception of the Middle Ages as a backward era “against
which the Renaissance was the reaction and the Reformation the great rebellion”
as itself a caricature of genuine Whig history, but even that distorted
picture captures the essential approach. Although Whig history draws on
Continental as well as British sources, it is essentially the story of
the rise and triumph of British liberties told from the victor’s perspective.
Founded
on a narrative of British Protestant exceptionalism, the Whig interpretation
developed in a particularly English context shaped by common law. 17th-century
lawyers first made the case that English liberties and constitutional forms
went back to time immemorial and that the Magna Carta guaranteed
liberty for all. Their arguments justified opposition to Charles I in the
1630s and 1640s, and later became the basis of Whig propaganda as the fledgling
party grew from the 1680s onward. Historical polemics that drew heavily
on a providential vision of England as God’s chosen nation tested by hardship
cast Whigs as the true defenders of English liberties and the Protestant
religion. Ironically, the most substantive 18th-century exposition of the
Whig view came from a French Huguenot, Paul Rapin de Thoyras, who explained
for a foreign readership Britain’s rise as a great power after a century
of internal conflict.5
Another
generation of party conflict from the 1780s to the 1830s sharpened Whig
arguments. Charles James Fox, the charismatic politician who led the Whigs
through their darkest years of opposition in the 1790s, planned a history
of the Glorious Revolution to revive the party’s image and refute David
Hume’s Tory history of England. A lesserknown Whig politician, Sir James
Mackintosh, took Fox’s project further with the intention of showing how
England had avoided the turmoil wrought by the French Revolution through
a study covering the period from 1688 to 1789. Mackintosh incorporated
sociological insights of the Scottish Enlightenment into a Whig framework
and expanded its view beyond England’s history to encompass Britain as
a whole. Although he amassed volumes of material, Mackintosh’s political
career and an opium addiction acquired in India prevented him from completing
the work. Mackintosh’s research instead provided a starting point for a
younger Whig whose work came to dominate 19th-century liberal historiography:
Thomas Babington Macaulay.
Circumstances
gave Macaulay a particularly receptive audience for what became the Whig
interpretation’s definitive statement. Fox and Mackintosh had blazed the
trail, while Sir Walter Scott, despite his Tory views, provided a literary
model. While Macaulay’s narrative recounted lost opportunities and disasters
along with triumphs, he insisted that Britain’s experience since 1688 had
been the history of physical, moral, and intellectual development. The
Whig party and its ideas lay behind the political achievement of combining
order with freedom that made progress possible.6 Macaulay’s analytical
framework appealed as much to readers as his vivid style and depth of knowledge,
and his History of England provided the literary and historical
counterpart to the Whig/Liberal dominance of British politics from 1832
to 1885.
Macaulay
presented a clear and obvious past ordered by the way in which it specifically
prepared the way for the future. His books appeared not only when the British
(and American) public was particularly receptive to such assumptions, but
at a stage that influenced the development of history as a modern academic
discipline in Britain. Even Victorian scholars like C. H. Firth who criticized
Macaulay acknowledged his influence and operated largely within the framework
he had created. G. M. Trevelyan, Macaulay’s greatnephew, practiced and
defended Whig history well into the 1930s, and George V drew heavily on
Trevelyan for a 1935 Silver Jubilee speech in which he took pride in the
fact that British liberties and institutions had survived the shocks that
had brought tyranny abroad. Although the Liberals who had inherited the
Whig mantle under William Gladstone faded into irrelevance after 1920,
and Macaulay’s work itself took on a dated air, Whig history remained the
foundation of a liberal consensus in the English-speaking world.
Understanding
the origins and impact of Whig history places Butterfield’s critique in
perspective and underlines the similarities between the Whig interpretation
and other teleological schemes. Butterfield insisted that historical writing
would become more Whig as abridged narratives ironed out the conflicts
and inconsistencies that complicate events. While partisan Tory or Catholic
writers might offer their own abridgements, Butterfield saw that such tragic
views would find fewer advocates than Whig triumphalism. The celebratory
Whig perspective of British history as a benign teleology leading to parliamentary
liberalism and representative institutions fit easily with the civil religion
that underlay dominant forms of Anglo-American culture. This perspective
provided a rhetorical form that deeply influenced academe and public consciousness
on both sides of the Atlantic for much of the 20th century.
The
“Grand Narrative” taught in Western civilization and great books programs
at Columbia University and the University of Chicago exemplified the phenomenon.
Independently, Will Durant developed a popularized version of a progressivist
Grand Narrative in his courses for working men. Differences in methodology
and sophistication aside, each of these projects taught the history of
Western civilization along Whig lines as an evolution toward liberal democracy,
which culminated in the 20th-century United States. They were designed
to make culture accessible to a mass audience and assimilate immigrants
into America’s Anglo- Saxon Protestant culture, and the Grand Narrative
provided an intellectual underpinning to the “vital center” of post-New
Deal American politics that Arthur Schlesinger discerned in 1949. It also
justified what Norman Davies has called the “Allied Scheme of History”
that grew from the two World Wars and depicted the secular liberalism of
Britain and the United States as the apotheosis of human development. However,
as even sympathetic critics noted, the Grand Narrative transformed the
richness of history into increasingly stale pabulum by the 1960s. Loss
of faith in the American dream of meritocratic, assimiliationist liberalism
cast the Grand Narrative into disrepute, but its influence lingered on
into the 1990s.
Marxism
provided another powerfully attractive Whiggish teleology, even though
it rejected liberalism and derived from a materialist rather than an idealist
perspective. Although Butterfield welcomed the Marxist emphasis on the
social and economic roots of conflict along with its challenge to Whig
pieties, he rejected Marxist history as an oversimplified scheme of economic
determinism. Radical sympathies that once had drawn historians to Marxism
often survived the late 20th-century challenge to its economic theory as
race and gender supplanted class as dominant categories of historical analysis.
Multiculturalism can easily be lampooned as an inverted Whig history that
proclaims the history of the West as a story of oppression and patriarchy.
As such, it tells more about today’s preoccupations than it does about
the past.
Butterfield
presented history as a creative act of imagination, an effort to see the
past on its own terms. The historian must enter into the existence and
minds of those he studies, and that task requires an appreciation of the
ideas, ambitions, and prejudices of the past. Realizing that the past lies
in a world unlike our own, Butterfield saw that the ability to enter into
minds unlike our own provides the avenue to understanding and appreciating
history. To perceive the significance of events and discern the connections
between them requires an imaginative effort derived from self-knowledge.
Instead of subordinating the past to present concerns, true history engages
the past on its own terms by making it the historian’s present. Like literature,
historical writing at its best involves an art that makes it as much a
venture of the personality as an act of the mind, and Butterfield thought
creative writers like Scott and Thomas Carlyle best exemplified that imaginative
effort.
History
involves science along with art because imagination draws upon technical
knowledge derived from close study. The historian’s passion for manuscripts
and sources reflects his desire to bring himself into a relationship with
the past and all its particularities. Following Leopold von Ranke, Butterfield
insisted that archival research provides the basis for seeing the past
essentially as it was. Like a scientist, the historian begins with a hypothesis
and then collects and examines evidence before adjusting the hypothesis
to account for previously unknown facts. The scientific problem of how
an observer’s presence might affect the subject of study resembles the
way in which a historian’s perspective distorts analysis. Where the Whig
interpretation diligently fits new material into the old story even when
it should alter the bearings of the whole subject, authentic historical
research readily submits its hypotheses to falsification. Butterfield saw
research as an analytic project that assembled events, their chronology,
and the connections between them into an “objective body of knowledge”
as a preliminary basis for interpretation.
Butterfield
resembled Lord Acton in emphasizing the objective character of historical
fact and method. Both men saw that close study of original sources was
key to knowing the past, and Butterfield claimed that in Acton—who had
introduced Rankean history into Britain—“the Whig historian reached his
highest consciousness.” The difference between them lies in Acton’s wholehearted
acceptance of the Whig “desire to come to a judgment of values, make history
answer questions and decide issues, and to give the historian the last
word in a controversy.” Butterfield warned that Whig history’s judgmental
impulse pulls imaginative sympathy back short of understanding and impedes
the task of elucidating the past. The desire for judgment transforms history
into a prosecution brief. Acton envisioned history as “the upholder of
that moral standard which the powers of earth and religion itself tend
constantly to depress.” He followed, consciously or otherwise, the Duc
de Broglie’s charge to “beware of too much explaining, lest we end by excusing.”
Butterfield saw this view as perilously close to the position that it would
be better to be “unhistorical than do anything that may lower the moral
dignity of history.” Historical study, he insisted, never enters the realm
where the words “condemn” or “excuse” have meaning. The moral realm lies
beyond the historian’s purview of discerning what happened and why.7
Butterfield’s
argument may superficially resemble a pernicious relativism that seeks
to explain away what civilized societies can only condemn, while Broglie’s
injunction carries considerable moral weight after the atrocities of the
20th century. Ironically, it was Butterfield who deplored the Whig tendency
to dismiss or overlook a generation’s sufferings by focusing on acquired
advantages and happy readjustments. Admitting the limits of history, he
described the search for moral understanding as a cry for prophesy. As
a religious utterance, however, such a cry deals with divine providence
more than with the empirical facts that are the historian’s only evidence
and interest. The historian has no special insight into providence and
its workings, and he can claim no particular standing for determining moral
responsibility. Far from acting as a judge, the historian stands as an
expert witness called to describe and explain the past. Ethics concern
the historian only in the way faulty moral reasoning has affected human
conduct.
Another
problem with passing historical judgment involves the long-term impact
of events. The way in which good can come of tragedy complicates the simple
allocation of blame or the more complex question of an event’s meaning.
Joseph Schumpeter’s description of how “creative destruction” drives economic
development indicates the problem. Butterfield cites the great fire of
London in 1666 as a catastrophe that allowed Charles II, Sir Christopher
Wren, and others to rebuild the city on a better plan. More broadly, he
also notes the split within Christendom created by the Reformation and
the way in which American independence changed the British Empire as cases
where people profited from the experience of what many at the time saw
as a disaster.8 A historian who passes judgment on the past in the style
famously parodied in Sellars and Yeatman’s 1066 and All That misses
Butterfield’s point that providence enables man to redeem mistakes, “changing
evil into good and necessity into opportunity.”9 More than the event itself,
the reconciling mind that salvages a situation draws another veil before
the factors that would inform an attempt at judgement.
The
sharpest rejoinder to Butterfield is that the historian can never really
see the past as it essentially was. Historical research cannot provide
a full corrective to the Whig fallacy because historians use documents
and other sources for purposes other than those for which they were compiled.
The original use of every relic from the past reflects a specific pattern
of activity, and historians impose their own categories on those relics
by putting them to a different use. But how else can observers draw different
conclusions from the same object or document? Butterfield may identify
the problem of anachronism, but he fails to resolve it because, given the
nature of historical study, present-centeredness is inescapable.
Such
a tu quoque argument, however, falls short of a refutation since
qualifications about what historians can know recur throughout Butterfield’s
writings. He appreciated that history involves seeing the past as it essentially
was rather than having a full and complete picture of events. If historians
cannot see the past except through their own prejudices and assumptions,
they can at least deliberately set those aside when undertaking historical
writing. While not omniscient, historians have the advantage of hindsight.
Understanding the past on its own terms means striving to see the past
objectively.
William
Anthony Hay is an assistant professor of history at Mississippi State University
and a senior fellow with the Foreign Policy Research Institute (www.fpri.org).
He is author of The Whig Revival, 1808–1830 (Palgrave Macmillan,
2005).
1 Herbert
Butterfield, The Whig Interpretation of History (G. Bell & Sons,
1931), 96.
2 Maurice
Cowling, “Sir Herbert Butterfield,” Proceedings of the British Academy
65 (1979): 596–97. C.T. McIntyre has made the dissenting notion the organizing
theme of his new intellectual biography Herbert Butterfield: Historian
as Dissenter (Yale University Press, 2004).
3 Butterfield,
George III and the Historians (Collins, 1957), 9.
4 Richard
Brent, “Butterfield’s Tories: ‘High Politics’ and the Writing of Modern
British Political History,” Historical Journal 30 (1987): 943–954.
5 Paul
Rapin de Thoyras, History of England, as Well Ecclesiastical as Civil
. . . Done into English from the French, 15 vols. (James and John Knapton,
1727–1731).
6 Thomas
Babbington Macaulay, The History of England from the Accession of James
II, 5 vols. (International Book Publishers),1: 15.
7 Whig
Interpretation, 109, 64–65, 112–17.
8 Christianity
and History (Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1950), 98–99.
9 The
Englishman and His History (Cambridge University Press, 1945), 116.
<top>
Join
the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking
Historically
Speaking: The Bulletin of the Historical Society
January/February
2005
Volume
VI, Number 3
IN
MEMORIAM: DANIEL J. BOORSTIN
Harold
D. Woodman
Daniel
J. Boorstin, one of the 20th century’s most prolific, insightful, and influential
historians, died at the age of 89 in Washington D.C. on February 28, 2004.
While so many in the profession in the post-World War II era were narrowing
their focus, Boorstin, like the Progressive historians early in the century,
sought to provide broader visions of the past, first in his interpretations
of American history and then in his investigations of aspects of the intellectual
history of Western civilization. And like the Progressive historians, Boorstin
was also a social critic, raising significant questions about both the
development of American society as well as the evolution of the historical
profession in the United States.
Boorstin’s
formal academic education was in the law rather than history. After earning
his bachelor’s degree at Harvard, he studied at Balliol College, Oxford
University as a Rhodes Scholar and read law at the Inner Temple in London.
He passed the English bar examinations in 1937 and become a barrister-at-law
before returning to the United States where in 1940 he earned a J.S.D.
at Yale University and two years later was admitted to the Massachusetts
bar. In the meantime he began his academic career in history, teaching
briefly at Harvard and at Swarthmore College before joining the University
of Chicago as an assistant professor in 1944. He remained at the University
of Chicago for twenty-five years, becoming the Preston and Sterling Morton
Distinguished Service Professor of History in 1964. During his tenure at
Chicago he was often invited to teach abroad. He was a Fulbright lecturer
at the University of Rome, a visiting professor of American history at
the University of Kyoto in Japan, and he lectured for the State Department
in Turkey, Iran, Nepal, India, and Ceylon. In 1961 he accepted an invitation
to inaugurate the chair in American History at the University of Paris,
and in 1964–65 he was Pitt Professor of American History and Institutions
and a Fellow of Trinity College at Cambridge University. He left the University
of Chicago in 1969 for the National Museum of History and Technology, a
part of the Smithsonian Institution in Washington, D.C., where he served
as Director and Senior Historian. In 1975 President Gerald Ford appointed
him Librarian of Congress, a position he held until retiring in 1987.
From
the beginning of his long and illustrious career, Boorstin elicited both
enthusiastic praise and sharp criticism. Because his degree was in law
rather than history, a few questioned his credentials as a historian. Boorstin
replied that his lack of formal training in history was a strength, not
a weakness, because it made him an “amateur.” “With the good fortune to
be permitted to be a historian without conventional credentials, I have
delighted in pursuing history for the love of it,” he wrote, and this opened
him to fresh and untraditional ways of thinking about the past: “An enamored
amateur need not be a genius to stay out of the ruts he has never been
trained in.” This is, of course, more than a bit disingenuous. He was well
aware of historical controversies, but he was impatient with many of them
and chose to stay out of the “ruts” and instead investigate other matters
he deemed more important.
These
other matters were more important for Boorstin not because they were so
obscure or esoteric, but because they were so obvious, so self-evident,
so commonplace that they were ignored or given inadequate attention by
historians. Although he called himself an intellectual historian—at least,
that was what his courses at the University of Chicago were called—he did
not deal with the great ideas that occupied the attention of most scholars
in American intellectual history at the time. Instead he centered his attention
on the ordinary, on the commonplace, on those things that occupied the
attention of most people in the past. Boorstin insisted that the study
of such things provided important insights into what people thought and
how and why they behaved as they did. In a brilliant essay, “The Historian:
‘A Wrestler With the Angel’” (he borrowed the phrase of the Dutch historian
J. H. Huizinga) he noted how documents that are popular and widely used
are apt “to have disappeared or been destroyed” as have homes, utensils,
and artifacts used by ordinary folk. What remain and thereby get most of
the attention of historians are religious and governmental documents and
very valuable but often unused or little used artifacts. Even a casual
glance at Boorstin’s writings reveals his remarkable ability to take the
ordinary—an event, an artifact, a way of doing something, a new phrase
entering the language—and give it meaning and significance by showing its
importance to the lives of people.
Boorstin’s
status as an amateur arose again when President Ford selected him to be
the Librarian of Congress. Some professional librarians opposed his nomination
because he had no training or experience as a librarian. He decided to
take the position, recalling Justice Felix Frankfurter’s words in a letter
to FDR: “The person to direct the national library of a great nation need
not be a professional librarian, but he should be someone who reads books,
makes books, loves books.” This certainly described Daniel Boorstin—and
during his twelve years as Librarian he sought to extend his love of reading
to a wider audience by encouraging people to visit the Library, by organizing
Library exhibitions, and by establishing the Center for the Book, which
seeks to stimulate reading and literacy. “We must face and defeat the twin
menaces of illiteracy and aliteracy—the inability to read and lack of the
will to read—if our citizens are to remain free and qualified to govern
themselves,” he wrote in a report to Congress in 1984. His successful effort
to transform the library for congress into a library for the people is
his lasting legacy as Librarian of Congress.
I’ve
already noted that Boorstin was in the tradition of the Progressive historians
in the breadth of his vision and in his role as a social critic. But he
differed from the Progressive historians in a number of important ways,
which sometimes elicited criticisms in the academy. Unlike the Progressives
and many of his contemporaries, Boorstin denied that history could be made
scientific —a position well within venerable traditions of historical writing
but at odds with recent historical scholarship. While many of his contemporaries
spoke of the “new” history which sought to apply theories and methods from
the social sciences to historical data to give scientific rigor to historical
analysis, Boorstin insisted that these approaches were “alien to the historian’s
search for nuance, flow, and the elusiveness of experience” and were “at
odds with his role as a literary artist.”
For
Boorstin, the historian as literary artist meant that the historian had
the obligation to write well, an obligation that he met in all his publications—from
occasional essays and lectures published in newspapers and popular magazines
to monographs and largescale studies of American and European history,
including a high school textbook in American history and the two-volume
Landmark History of the American People, a beautifully illustrated
history for young people. But the notion of the historian as literary artist
also meant writing in the pattern of Edward Gibbon, whose History of
the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire had “an especially intimate
significance” for him, Boorstin wrote, because Gibbon’s work was free of
the dogma and doctrine that dominated the historical writings of his contemporaries
and of so much of later historical scholarship. For Gibbon “there are no
trivia,” he wrote. “Human habits, utterances, exclamations, and emotions
are the very essence of his history—not mere raw material for distilling
‘forces’ and ‘movements.’ The more vividly we see them, the better we know
our subject.” Boorstin’s analysis of Gibbon explains his own view of the
role of the historian as literary artist and his particular brand of conservatism:
“Just as Gibbon was not imprisoned in the jargon and special conceits of
his age, so perhaps we need not be imprisoned in ours.”
Like
the Progressive historian Frederick Jackson Turner, Boorstin identified
a unique American character, but, unlike Turner, he saw that character
not merely as a response to the western frontier but rather as a response
to the frontier of opportunity. Recognizing these available opportunities
and, indeed, taking those opportunities wherever they were, Americans eschewed
doctrine and theory, meeting and solving problems and molding their political
and social institutions in a pragmatic and open-ended way. The result was
an American character and way of life with many of the qualities—and weaknesses—that
Turner had described. This American way of life therefore could neither
be exported nor imposed upon others—even though Americans periodically
thought otherwise. “The most fruitless venture on which any people has
ever engaged is the effort to sell an ‘American way of life’ to people
from the Himalayas to Timbuktu,” he wrote in an essay in New York Times
(April 29, 1959), a position that seems relevant, if still controversial,
today.
Some
of the criticism of Boorstin was based upon his political conservatism.
While a student at Harvard he was briefly a member of the Communist Party;
in his testimony before the House Committee on Un-American Activities in
1953 he named other members that he knew. More than a decade later some
students at the University of Chicago used his testimony to justify disrupting
his classes and in other ways harassing him, actions that undoubtedly played
a role in his decision to leave the university. Boorstin’s opposition to
affirmative action and other policies that today we would term “politically
correct” led to further attacks, including outrageously mistakenly charges
by a few that he was a racist. In one of the few instances in which he
entered in public political conflict, Boorstin answered these charges in
a scathing satire, The Sociology of the Absurd (1969).
Although
conservative in his politics, Boorstin was adamant in his opposition to
doctrinal ideologies, adopting a truly liberal, openminded, and tolerant
point of view in his opinions and in his relationships with others, including,
as I can personally vouch, with his students and colleagues: “I have observed
that the world has suffered far less from ignorance than from pretensions
to knowledge. It is not skeptics or explorers but fanatics and ideologues
who menace decency and progress. No agnostic ever burned anyone at the
stake or tortured a pagan, a heretic, or an unbeliever,” he wrote.
Boorstin
had ample personal experience with the intolerance he deplored—in his harassment
at the university and in events from his youth. He was born in Atlanta
where his father, an attorney, served as Governor John Marshall Slaton’s
private secretary and became involved in the defense of Leo Frank, a local
Jewish businessman falsely accused and then convicted of rape and murder
and sentenced to death. When Governor Slaton reduced Frank’s death penalty
to life imprisonment, leading to the lynching of Frank and surging anti-Semitism,
Boorstin’s father and his brother and other members of the family decided
it would be best for them to leave Atlanta. They moved to Tulsa, Oklahoma,
where Boorstin grew up and went to school before leaving for Harvard.
Boorstin’s
published output was truly prodigious—more than twenty books—many translated
into some twenty-five languages— and hundreds of essays in the public press.
He also found the time to become a prolific editor: some thirty volumes
in the Chicago History of American Civilization series; An American
Primer, a two-volume collection of documents, each introduced and discussed
by a leading historian; and several other volumes as well. His beautifully
written books and essays reveal his enormous learning, his innovative approach,
and his originality, which won him prizes and public accolades. His readership
extended far beyond the academy; many of his books became best-sellers
in days when most academic historians seemed to be writing for a few specialists
rather than for the general public.
In
his first book, The Mysterious Science of the Law (1941), an analysis
of Sir William Blackstone’s Commentaries on the Laws of England,
Boorstin argued that Americans used the conservative Tory views of Blackstone
to understand and perpetuate ancient English law in order to justify their
opposition to the English during the Revolution. The result, Boorstin concluded,
was a revolution that was conservative and legalistic rather than ideologically
revolutionary. An emphasis on experience rather than theoretical speculation
was a central element in Thomas Jefferson’s thought, Boorstin argued in
his second book, The Lost World of Thomas Jefferson (1948).
In
1953 Boorstin published The Genius of American Politics, a revision
of his 1952 Charles R. Walgreen Foundation Lectures, in which he briefly
extended his argument that law and experience rather than philosophy and
ideology were the basis for American thought and politics. In the following
two decades he spelled out his interpretation in detail in a massive, award-winning
trilogy: The Americans: The Colonial Experience (1958), winner of
the Bancroft Prize; The Americans: The National Experience (1965),
given the Francis Parkman Prize; and The Americans: The Democratic Experience
(1973), awarded the Pulitzer Prize.
With
the publication of The Genius of American History and the trilogy
that followed, Boorstin was labeled a “consensus” historian, and correctly
so, although he did not use the term or acknowledge his being part of a
“school” of historians that included, among others, Richard Hofstadter
and Louis Hartz and scholars such as Leo Marx and Henry Nash Smith in the
emerging new field of American Studies. Critics argued that the consensus
historians were exponents of “American exceptionalism,” that they glorified
the American past by insisting that the American experience created a society
that differed from that of Europe because it lacked the sharp class divisions
and ideological conflicts; consensus history, some argued, was little more
than Cold War propaganda.
Boorstin
did argue in favor of the notion of American exceptionalism in a 1944 essay,
which he reprinted in a collection a half-century later. But to argue that
his work was Cold War propaganda is nonsense. Americans did somehow manage
to escape most of the horrors that overcame many countries, and an attempt
to explain how and why this happened seemed in the aftermath of World War
II a reasonable problem for historians to tackle. And it remains a reasonable
problem to this day.
It
is truly a remarkable indication of Boorstin’s energy and ability that
while writing his trilogy, The Americans, and working full-time,
first at the University of Chicago and then at the Smithsonian Institution,
he somehow found the time to write and publish several additional books
commenting on various aspects of American history and contemporary society.
The most famous of these is The Image, or What Happened to the American
Dream (1962), a study that shows how technology and the media transformed
the ways in which Americans experienced reality, that is, what they perceived
as reality. Heroes became celebrities who were well known for their “well-knownness”
and news became manufactured “pseudo-events” rather than reports of real
events.
When
nominated to be Librarian of Congress, Boorstin promised senators who were
considering his appointment that he would not use his workday for research
and writing. He kept his promise, leaving his typewriter at home—he never,
to my knowledge, adopted the computer—but he continued to write on his
own time on weekends and during pre-dawn hours before coming to work at
the Library. Astonishingly, this schedule hardly slowed his scholarly productivity.
During his tenure as Librarian of Congress, he published several books
about American history, including a textbook, and in 1983 the first volume
of a massive new trilogy.
In
this new trilogy Boorstin provided popular and accessible—but never superficial
—analyses of what he considered to be key aspects of the intellectual history
of Western civilization. The first volume, The Discoverers: A History
of Man’s Search to Know His World and Himself (1983) deals with people
who found new places and new ways of looking at the world in which they
lived. Two more volumes in the trilogy followed Boorstin’s retirement as
Librarian of Congress. The Creators: A History of Heroes of the Imagination
(1992) deals with the arts, and The Seekers: The Story of Man’s Continuing
Quest to Understand His World (1998) deals with philosophers and other
thinkers.
In
his essay “The Intimacy of Gibbon’s Decline and Fall,” Boorstin
wrote: “Serious scholars do not doubt the originality or the significance
of Gibbon’s work. Still, he has not become the founder of a ‘school.’ He
has not taken a place as the originator of any large new conceptual framework,
or any novel way of pigeonholing the human past. I will suggest that this
is a clue to the intimacy of his message about that past, and what he can
tell each of us about the role of people in the grand chronicle of empires
and civilizations.”
And
I suggest that these words may apply to the work of Daniel J. Boorstin.
He is survived by his wife, Ruth, three sons, four grandchildren, many
friends, colleagues, former students, and millions of readers all over
the world.
We
shall all miss him.
Harold
D. Woodman is emeritus professor of history at Purdue University. He is
the author of King Cotton and His Retainers: Financing and Marketing
the Cotton Crop of the South, 1800–1925 (University of South Carolina
Press, 1990) and coauthor of Conflict and Consensus in American History,
9th ed. (Houghton Mifflin, 1997).
<top>
Join
the Historical Society and subscribe to Historically Speaking