20th World Congress of Philosophy Logo

Theoretical Ethics

Humanity Educating Philosophy

Jeffrey W. Bulger
Utah Valley State College
Bulgerje@uvsc.edu

bluered.gif (1041 bytes)

ABSTRACT: This treatise is a contribution towards the understanding of why humankind cannot agree on the foundation of morality and why moral pluralism is the logical constitution of moral reality. The synergistic-reflective-equilibrium model is the model that will describe how persons can make moral decisions as pluralistic agents. If this model is correct, then it will not be a new discovery, rather, it will be a new description of how pluralistic agents do in fact make moral decisions. This synergistic-reflective-equilibrium description should then be useful not only in giving a fuller understanding of how moral decisions ought to be made, but also how moral philosophy can be united into a pluralistic collective whole. The first part of this paper defines the synergistic-reflective-equilibrium mode. It briefly explains how it is a combination of both the theory model of moral decision-making and the intuition model of moral decision-making. The second part of this paper defines mid-level principles and explains how they are a natural development of the synergistic-reflective-equilibrium method. It will then be shown that both Mill and Kant used this method in their own moral theories. Lastly, it will be shown how "weighing and balancing" and "specification" are integral components in this model and were also practiced by Mill and Kant in their moral systems.

bluered.gif (1041 bytes)

Introduction

This treatise is a contribution towards the understanding of why humankind cannot agree on the foundation of morality and why moral pluralism is the logical constitution of moral reality. The synergistic-reflective-equilibrium model is the model that will describe how persons can make moral decisions as pluralistic agents. If this model is correct, then it will not be a new discovery, rather, it will be a new description of how pluralistic agents do in fact make moral decisions. This synergistic-reflective-equilibrium description should then be useful not only in giving a fuller understanding of how moral decisions ought to be made, but also how moral philosophy can be united into a pluralistic collective whole.

I. The Synergistic-Reflective-Equilibrium Model

The synergistic-reflective-equilibrium model is the position in which the justification of what is right or wrong is done by using neither a pure theory model, nor a pure intuition model. The synergistic-reflective-equilibrium model is a back-and-forth process—starting with particulars and going to the general and back to the particulars and so on and so forth. This is a constant process that never really comes to closure as new decisions are constantly having to be made. As Kant said:

Virtue is always in progress and yet always starts from the beginning. –It is always in progress because, considered objectively, it is an ideal and unattainable, while yet constant approximation to it is a duty. That it always starts from the beginning has a subjective basis in human nature, which is affected by inclinations because of which virtue can never settle down in peace and quiet with its maxims adopted once and for all but, if it is not rising, is unavoidably sinking. For, moral maxims, unlike technical ones cannot be based on habit (since this belongs to the natural constitution of the will’s determination); on the contrary, if the practice of virtue were to become a habit the subject would suffer loss to that freedom in adopting his maxims which distinguishes an action done from duty. (1)

The synergistic-reflective-equilibrium model synergistically combines the theory model and the intuition model using the process of reflective-equilibrium. It combines the covering-precept model in which justification is from the "top-down", and the individual-case model in which justification is from the bottom-up, using the process of reflective-equilibrium in which individuals take their accepted intuitions, norms, and theories, mirror them back and forth, making appropriate changes, until an equilibrium or balance is achieved.

II. Mid-Level Principles And The Synergistic-Reflective-Equilibrium Model

When adopting this synergistic-reflective-equilibrium model, there is a natural development of "mid-level principles". These are abstract principles that are justified by both the theory model and the intuition model. These mid-level principles will be either derived from, congruent with, or at least not in conflict with the theories and/or intuitions. These mid-level principles are partial substantive developments of abstract or ethereal theories, and the partial theory development of practical or intuitional choices resulting in principles that are easily accessible on a regular basis.

Mid-level principles may be likened to that of Mill’s secondary principles. Mill believed that people live most of their lives by appealing to secondary principles. It is only when there are conflicting secondary principles that there is ever the need to appeal to the primary principle of utility—the greatest happiness principle. We must remember that only in these cases of conflict between secondary principles is it requisite that first principles should be appealed to. There is no case of moral obligation in which some secondary principle is not involved. (2)

Kant in his Metaphysics of Morals divides his investigation of the doctrine of duties into two parts. The first three-fifths of the book is devoted to The Doctrine of Right which deals with individual rights, or duties that are established by external laws, i.e., judicially. The second two-fifths of the book is devoted to The Doctrine of Virtue which deals with ethics or duties that cannot be given by external laws. The following quotes show how the differences between the doctrine of right and the doctrine of virtue comes about through the use of the synergistic-reflective-equilibrium model.

One can think of the relation of end to duty in two ways: one can begin with the end [intuitive choices] and seek out the maxim of actions [mid-level principles] in conformity with duty [theory] [bottom-up or intuitive approach] or, on the other hand, one can begin with the maxim of actions [mid-level principles] in conformity with duty [theory] and seek out the end [intuitive choice] that is also a duty [theory] [top-down or theory approach]. –The doctrine of right takes the first way [bottom-up]. What end anyone wants to set for his action is left to his free choice. The maxim of his action, however, is determined a priori, namely, that the freedom of the agent could coexist with the freedom of every other in accordance with a universal law.

But ethics takes the opposite way [top-down]. … Hence in ethics the concept of duty [theory] will lead to ends [intuitive choices] and will have to establish maxims [mid-level-principles] with respect to ends we ought to set ourselves [theory], grounding them in accordance with moral principles. … Only an end that is also a duty can be called a duty of virtue.…

What essentially distinguishes a duty of virtue from a duty of right is that external constraint to the latter kind of duty is morally possible, whereas the former is based only on free self-constraint. (3)

The mid-level principles from the doctrine of right are those rights and liberties that are necessary for the making of social decisions. In a pluralistic environment, e.g., when making social decisions, with a group that may hold to many different theories and/or intuitions, it is common, for example, in the United States, to appeal to the Constitution which can be thought of as mid-level principles. The Constitution thus consists of basic rights and liberties that most "participants" find either derivable from, compatible with, or at least not in conflict with their theories and/or intuitions as it relates to the freedom of all citizens.

A law that is so holy (inviolable) that it is already a crime even to call it in doubt in a practical way, and so to suspend its effect for a moment, is thought as if it must have arisen not from human beings but from some highest, flawless lawgiver; and that is what the saying "All authority is from God" means. This saying is not an assertion about the historical basis of the civil constitution; it instead sets forth an idea as a practical principle of reason: the principle that the presently existing legislative authority ought to be obeyed, whatever its origin. (4)

The mid-level principles from the doctrine of virtue are those ends that are also duties. ‘They are one’s own perfection and the happiness of others.

Only the concept of an end that is also a duty, a concept that belongs exclusively to ethics, establishes a law for maxims of actions by subordinating the subjective end (that everyone has) to the objective end (that everyone ought to make his end). The imperative "You out to make this or that (e.g., the happiness of others) your end" has to do with the matter of choice (an object). Now no free action is possible unless the agent also intends an end (which is the matter of choice). Hence, if there is an end that is also a duty, the only condition that maxims of actions, as means to ends, must contain is that of qualifying for a possible giving of universal law. (5)

These mid-level principles are mutually constraining in that each principle limits the exercise of the other principles through the process of weighing and balancing, and specification.

When persons do find themselves having to act from a motive of duty, it still may be the case that they will not have to appeal to their theory or first principle. During the whole past duration of the human species mankind has already determined many positive beliefs as to what are moral actions and have developed these mid-level principles by which actions can be determined.

People talk as if … at the moment when some man feels tempted to meddle with the property or life of another, he had to begin considering for the first time whether murder and theft are injurious to human happiness. … [M]ankind must by this time have acquired positive beliefs, [i.e., mid-level principles] … .

To consider the rules of morality as improvable is one thing; to pass over the intermediate generalization entirely and endeavor to test each individual action directly by the first principle [theory] is another. It is a strange notion that the acknowledgment of a first principle [theory] is inconsistent with the admission of secondary ones [mid-level principles].

There exists no moral system under which there do not arise unequivocal cases of conflicting obligation, [mid-level principles]. These are the real difficulties, the knotty points both in the theory of ethics and in the conscientious guidance of personal conduct. [When there are] moral laws, [mid-level principles], all claiming independent authority, there is no common umpire entitled to interfere between them; their claims to precedence one over another rest on little better than sophistry, and, unless determined, … [they] afford a free scope for the action of personal desires and partialities. We must remember that only in these cases of conflict between secondary principles [mid-level principles] is it requisite that first principles, [Theory], should be appealed to. There is no case of moral obligation in which some secondary principle [mid-level principle] is not involved. (6)

III. Weighing And Balancing

Theories, mid-level principles, and intuitions are often times composed of many prima facie "rights and liberties" that have to be weighed and balanced. This weighing and balancing process is an attempt to maximize all competing rights and liberties. All rights and liberties exist in a reciprocal relationship that is mutually constraining resulting in the necessity to balance. For example, no one could rationally hold to the view that freedom of speech is an absolute right in the sense that all persons have the liberty to yell fire in a crowded theater if they so desired. In other words, the right of freedom of speech needs to be weighed and balanced with the right of safe assembly. (7) No rights and/or liberties are absolute, rather they must be specified and balanced with all other competing rights and/or liberties.

There exists no moral system under which there do not arise unequivocal cases of conflicting obligation. … They are overcome practically, with greater or with less success, according to the intellect and virtue of the individual. (8)

Under the section above on the Development Of Mid-Level Principles we saw how Mill emphasized this point stating

that only in these cases of conflict between secondary principles [mid-level principles] is it requisite that first principles, [Theory], should be appealed to. There is no case of moral obligation in which some secondary principle [mid-level principle] is not involved. (9)

Kant argues that sometimes the certain use of freedom, (like freedom of speech), can actually become a hindrance to other freedoms in accordance with universal law, (like freedom of safe assembly). Coercion against those who try to exercise the hindering freedoms is therefore authorized.

… Now whatever is wrong is a hindrance to freedom in accordance with universal laws. But coercion is a hindrance or resistance to freedom. Therefore, if a certain use of freedom is itself a hindrance to freedom in accordance with universal laws (i.e., wrong), coercion that is opposed to this (as a hindering of a hindrance to freedom is consistent with freedom in accordance with universal laws , that is, it is right. Hence there is connected with right by the principle of contradiction an authorization to coerce someone who infringes upon it.

… [For example], coercion which constrains everyone to pay his debts can coexist with the freedom of everyone, including that of debtors, in accordance with a universal external law. Right and authorization to use coercion therefore mean one and the same thing. (10)

The question now can be raised as to whether this idea of mid-level principles as not being absolute is contrary to Kant’s moral conception of absolutes. After all Kant did argue that there could never be any conflict of obligations, whereas Mill argues that conflict of obligations will arise under any moral system. In regards to conflicting duties Kant said:

A conflict of duties would be a relation between them in which one of them would cancel the other (wholly or in part). —But since duty and obligation are concepts that express the objective practical necessity of certain actions and two rules opposed to each other cannot be necessary at the same time, if its is a duty to act in accordance with one rule, to act in accordance with the opposite rule is not a duty but even contrary to duty; so a collision of duties and obligations is inconceivable. However, a subject may have, in a rule he prescribes to himself, two grounds of obligation one or the other of which is not sufficient to put him under obligation, so that one of them is not a duty. —When two such grounds conflict with each other, practical philosophy says, not that the stronger obligation takes precedence, but that the stronger ground of obligation prevails. (11)

It should be noticed that what Kant is talking about here and what is being expressed with the concept of mid-level principles is totally compatible. The mid-level principles do not conflict in the sense that one principle says that persons have freedom of speech and another principle says that persons do not have freedom of speech. Rather, the weighing and balancing has to do with, for example, freedom of speech in combination with freedom of safe assembly. Therefore, ethical duties are wide obligations in which various duties mutually constrain each other, e.g., love of one’s neighbor in general by love of one’s parents.

… if the law can prescribe only the maxim of actions, not actions themselves, this is a sign that it leaves a playroom for free choice in following (complying with) the law, that is, that the law cannot specify precisely in what way one is to act and how much one is to do by the action for an end that is also a duty. – But a wide duty is not to be taken as permission to make exceptions to the maxim of actions but only as permission to limit one maxim of duty by another (e.g., love of one’s neighbor in general by love of one’s parents), by which in fact the field for the practice of virtue is widened. – The wider the duty, therefore, the more imperfect is a man’s obligation to action. (12)

IV. Specification

Specification is the process in which theories and mid-level principles are developed conceptually and shaped normatively, so that they can be applied to particular circumstances. Each new decision, within new circumstances, generally requires that our abstract theories and/or mid-level principles be interpreted in terms of how they can and/or should be applied to practical life. As Kant said:

The doctrine of right has to do only with narrow duties, whereas ethics has to do with wide duties. Hence the doctrine of right, which by its nature must determine duties strictly (precisely), has no more need of general directions (a method) as to how to proceed in judging than does pure mathematics; instead, it certifies its method by what it does.–But ethics, because of the latitude it allows in its imperfect duties, unavoidably leads to questions that call upon judgment to decide how a maxim is to be applied in particular cases, and indeed in such a way that judgment provides another (subordinate) maxim (and one can always ask for yet another principle for applying this maxim to cases that may arise). So ethics falls into a casuistry, which has no place in the doctrine of right. (13)

The doctrine of right wants to be sure that what belongs to each has been determined (with mathematical exactitude). Such exactitude cannot be expected in the doctrine of virtue, [ethics], which cannot refuse some room for exceptions. (14)

Mill also said:

It is not the fault of any creed, but of the complicated nature of human affairs, that rules of conduct cannot be so framed as to require no exceptions, and that hardly any kind of action can safely be laid down as either always obligatory or always condemnable. There is no ethical creed which does not temper the rigidity of its laws by giving a certain latitude, under the moral responsibility of the agent, for accommodation to peculiarities of circumstances. (15)

As reasonable as this may sound, Mill has been criticized for presenting a flippant philosophy in which there are not absolutes and as a result most any action could be justified as long as it resulted in the greatest amount of happiness, i.e., they argue that Mill’s moral approach would allow the performing of "immoral" or "unjust" actions as long as they resulted in the greatest amount of happiness. The following is an example of how Mill addressed such criticisms.

Again, utility is often summarily stigmatized as an immoral doctrine by giving it the name of "expediency." … But the expedient, in the sense in which it is opposed to the right, generally means that which is expedient for the particular interest of the agent himself. … When it means anything better than this, it means that which is expedient for some immediate object, some temporary purpose, but which violates a rule whose observance is expedient in a much higher degree. The expedient, in this sense, instead of being the same thing with the useful, is a branch of the hurtful. Thus it would often be expedient, for the purpose of getting over some momentary embarrassment, or attaining some object immediately useful to ourselves or others, to tell a lie. But inasmuch as the cultivation in ourselves of a sensitive feeling on the subject of veracity is one of the most useful, and the enfeeblement of that feeling one of the most hurtful, things to which our conduct can be instrumental; and inasmuch as any, even unintentional, deviation from truth does that much toward weakening the trustworthiness of human assertion, which is not only the principal support of all present social well-being, but the insufficiency of which does more than any one thing that can be named to keep back civilization, virtue, everything on which human happiness on the largest scale depends—we feel that the violation, for a present advantage, of a rule of such transcendent expediency is not expedient, and that he who for the sake of convenience to himself or to some other individual, does what depends on him to deprive mankind of the good, and inflict upon them the evil, involved in the greater or less reliance which they can place in each other’s words, acts the part of one of their worst enemies. (16)

Later on Mill argues that: "Justice implies something which is not only right to do, and wrong not to do, but which some individual person can claim from us as his moral right." (17) "To have a right, then, is, I conceive, to have something which society ought to defend men in the possession of." (18) Mill presents five universal principles of justice and injustice that he believed were as close to being absolute as is possible. They were the following: 1. "unjust to deprive anyone of his personal liberty, his property, or any other thing which belongs to him by law." … 2. "legal rights of which he is deprived may be rights which ought not to have belonged to him." … 3. "considered just that each person should obtain that (whether good or evil) which he deserves, and unjust that he should obtain a good or be made to undergo an evil which he does not deserve." … 4. "unjust to break faith with anyone: to violate an engagement, ether express or implied, or disappoint expectations raised by or own conduct." … 5. "inconsistent with justice to be partial—to show favor or preference to one person over another in matter in which favor and preference do not properly apply." (19)

Justice is a name for certain classes of moral rules which concern the essentials of human well-being more nearly, and are therefore of more absolute obligation, than any other rules for the guidance of life; and the notion which we have found to be of the essence of the idea of justice—that of a right residing in an individual—implies and testifies to this more binding obligation. (20)

This is in total accord with what Kant had to say about conflicting obligations when he said:

When two such grounds conflict with each other, practical philosophy says, not that the stronger obligation takes precedence, but that the stronger ground of obligation prevails. …

A principle that makes certain actions duties is a practical law. A rule that the agent himself makes his principle on subjective grounds is called his maxim; hence, different agents can have very different maxims with regard to the same law. (21)

The categorical imperative, which as such only affirms what obligation is, is: act upon a maxim that can also hold as a universal law.

One of the most important concepts in the understanding of Kant’s philosophy of ethical duties is that the moral law can only prescribe maxims not actions. In fact in his book, The Metaphysics of Morals The Doctrine of Virtue, he as an entire section entitled, "Ethics Does Not Give Laws for Action (Right Does That), but Only for Maxims of Actions" devoting sections VI-IX to this subject. The following quotes should take away any doubts whether Kant’s philosophy is in accord with mid-level principles.

… if the law can prescribe only the maxim of actions, not actions themselves, this is a sign that it leaves a playroom for free choice in following (complying with) the law, that is, that the law cannot specify precisely in what way one is to act and how much one is to do by the action for an end that is also a duty. – But a wide duty is not to be taken as permission to make exceptions to the maxim of actions but only as permission to limit one maxim of duty by another (e.g., love of one’s neighbor in general by love of one’s parents), by which in fact the field for the practice of virtue is widened. – The wider the duty, therefore, the more imperfect is a man’s obligation to action; as he, nevertheless, brings closer to narrow duty (duties of right) the maxim of complying with wide duty (in his disposition), so much the more perfect is his virtuous action. (22)

Kant talks directly about the concept of specification at the end of discussion of the elements of ethics when he says:

These (duties of virtue) do not really call for a special chapter in the system of pure ethics. … They are only rules modified in accordance with differences of the subjects to whom the principle of virtue (in terms of what is formal) is applied in cases that come up in experience (the material). Hence, like anything divided on an empirical basis, they do not admit of a classification that could be guaranteed to be complete. … How should one behave, for example, toward human beings who are in a state of moral purity or depravity? Toward the cultivated or the crude? Toward the learned or the unschooled, and toward the learned in so far as they use their science as members of polite society or outside society, as specialists in their field (scholars)? Toward those whose learning is pragmatic or those in whom it proceeds more from spirit and taste? How should people be treated in accordance with their differences in rank, age, sex, health, prosperity or poverty, and so forth? These questions do not yield so many different kinds of ethical obligation (for there is only one, that of virtue as such), but only so many different ways of applying it (corollaries). Hence they cannot be presented as sections of ethics and members of the division of a system (which must proceed a priori from a rational concept), but can only be appended to the system. (23)

As can be seen from the above quotes both Mill and Kant would agree and approve of the concept of mid-level principles and how they are principles that need to be weighed and balanced, and specified for particular actions.

Conclusion

The synergistic-reflective-equilibrium model not only gives us a clearer philosophical understanding of how moral decisions are in fact made, but, more importantly, it helps in the understanding of how moral agents ought to make moral decisions both individually and as members of a pluralistic society.

bluered.gif (1041 bytes)

Notes

(1) Kant, Metaphysics of Morals, p. 167, [6:409]

(2) Mill, Utilitarianism, p. 25.

(3) Kant, Metaphysics of Morals; The Doctrine of Virtue, p. 147-148, [6:382-383].

(4) Kant, Metaphysics of Morals; The Doctrine of Right, p. 95, [6:319]

(5) Kant, Metaphysics of Morals; The Doctrine of Virtue, p. 152, [6:389].

(6) Mill, Utilitarianism, p. 25.

(7) As the old saying goes; "the right for me to swing my fists ends at the tip of your nose."

(8) Mill, Utilitarianism, p. 25

(9) Ibid., p. 25.

(10) Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals; The Doctrine of Right, (1785), Translated by Mary Gregor, (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996), pp. 25-26, [6:231-232].

(11) Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals; Preface to Doctrine of Right, pp. 16-17, [6:224].

(12) Ibid., p. 153, [6:390]

(13) Ibid., pp. 168-169, [6:411].

(14) Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals; The Doctrine of Right, p. 26, [6:233]

(15) Mill, Utilitarianism, p. 25.

(16) Ibid., p. 22.

(17) Ibid., p. 49.

(18) Ibid., p. 52.

(19) Ibid., pp. 42-45.

(20) Ibid., p. 58.

(21) Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals; Preface to Doctrine of Right, pp. 16-17, [6:224-225].

(22) Ibid., p. 153, [6:390].

(23) Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals; The Doctrine of Virtue, pp. 214, [6:468-469].

bluered.gif (1041 bytes)

 

Back to the Top

20th World Congress of Philosophy Logo

Paideia logo design by Janet L. Olson.
All Rights Reserved

 

Back to the WCP Homepage